Should press de liable or not \english\

SHOULD PRESS BELIABLE OR NOT?
       Recent years have increased legalaccountability of producers and
    advertisers for providing SAFEproducts and RELIABLE information  to
    customers.  A  government influences      a  wide  range  of market
    operations from licensingrequirements  to  contract  actions.  That
    control announces and enforcesdetermined norms of quality.
       Each of these regulations is designed  to protect consumers from
    being hurt or CHEATED by defects inthe goods and services they buy.
    This  matter,  when  producers look  to  the law rather than to the
    market to establish and maintain newstandards of quality (of  their
    goods),  shows, that modern markethas an ability of selfregulation.
    But it also shows anotherunbelievable feature:  consumers are  both
    incapable  of  rationally assessing  risks and unaware of their own
    ignorance.
       Companies and corporations allover the world are  systematically
    inclined  to  SHIRK  on quality andthat without the threat of legal
    liability may subject theircustomers or other people to serious  risk
    of harm from their products if itcould save money by doing so.
       According to this point of view,  for  most  goods and services,
    consumers are POWERLESS to getproducers to satisfy their demand for
    safe,  high-quality  products!  The unregulated  market lets unfair
    producers to pass on others thecosts of their mistakes.
       Legal liability is ready tocorrect  these «market  failures»  by
    creating   a  special  mechanism (feedback),  regulating  relations
    between producers and customers.Unfair producers should be punished
    and their exposure is increasing.
       One market,however, hascompletely ESCAPED the imposition of legal
    liability.  The market for politicalinformation  remains  genuinely
    ee  of  legally  imposed qualityobligations.  The electronic mass
    media are subject to more extensivegovernment regulation than  paid
    media,  but  in  their  role  as suppliers of political information,
    nothing is required  to  meet  any externally  established  quality
    standards.
       In fact, those, who gather  and report  the news,  have no legal
    obligations to be competent, thorough or disinterested.  And those,
    who publish or broadcast it, have nolegal obligation to warrant its
    truthfulness,  to   guarantee  its   relevance,   to   assure   its
    completeness.
       The thing is: Should thepolitical information they provide fail,
    for example,  to be truthful, relevant,  or complete,  the costs of
    this  failure will not be paid bypress.  Instead they will be borne
    by the citizens.  Should theinformation intrude the privacy  of  an
    individual   or   destroy   without justification  an  individual’s
    reputation — again, the cost willnot be borne by producer of it.
       This side of «activity»of  producers  of  harmful  or  defective
    information (goods,  services, etc)practically is not acknowledged.
    Producers of most goods andservices  are  considered  worlds  APART
    from  the  press in kind,  not justin degree.  Holding producers in
    ordinary markets to ever higherstandards of liability  is  seen  as
    PROCOMSUMER.   Proposing  holding the  press  to  any  standard  of
    liability for political informationis seen as  ANTIDEMOCRATIC.  The
    press is constitutionally obligatedto check on the government.
       Most of policymakers justifylegal liability for harms, caused by
    goods and services and quite limitedliability for harms,  caused by
    information. Liability for defectiveconsumer products is PREDICATED
    on a market failure.  As for«unfair» producers,  power of  possible
    profits  PREVENT  consumers  fromtranslating their true preferences
    for  safety  and  quality  into effective  demand.   So,   customer
    preferences  remain  outside  thesafety and quality decision-making
    process of producers.  Today,  it’llbe a  new  mechanism  to  force
    producers to follow customers truepreferences.
       Lack of liability  for defectiveor harmful political information
    can be predicated only on adifferent kind of supposed market failure
     — not a failure of   the market toSUPPLY the LEVEL of safety that
    customers want but its failure tosupply  the  amount  of  political
    information that society shouldhave.  Some experts say,  that free
    market has tendency to produce«too  little»  correct  information,
    especially political information.
       The thing is: politicalinformation is  a  public good and it has
    many characteristics of a publicgood. That is a product  that  many
    people  value  and  use  but  only few will pay for.  Factual(real)
    information cannot easily berestricted to direct  purchasers.  Many
    people  benefit who do not pay forit because the market cannot find
    the way to charge them.  As you can  see,  providers  of  political
    information  try to get as muchprofit as possible spreading it,  so
    they HAVE TO supply «toolittle» info. Otherwise — the market FAILS!
       Here is another reason. Someanalysts consider that the market also
    fails because of low demand. Even ifsuppliers could «earn all their
    money»,  they wouldn’t providethe socially optimal amount of  info!
    Private  demand  for political infowill never be the same as social
    demand. And it will never reflectits full social value.
       If it  were  true,  that political  information  was   regularly
    underproduced  by  the  market, there  would  be  cause for serious
    concern that might well justifygenerous sibsidies — in the form  of
    freedom  from  liability  for theharms they cuase — for information
    providers.  But a proper look atmodern market shows that  producers
    of political information  have developed a wide range of strategies
    for increasing the benefits of theirefforts  to  solve  the  public
    good problem.
       The most  obvious  example  of a  spontaneously generated market
    solution to the public good problem is  ADVERTISING.  By  providing
    revenue  in  proportion  to  the relative size of the audience (for
    radio  &  TV)  or  the readership  (for  magazines  &  newspapers),
    advertisers play a SIGNIFICANT rolein the internalizing process. In
    effect,  the sale of advertising ata price that varies according to
    the   number   of   recipients  permits  information  producers  to
    appropriate the benefits ofproviding a  product  that  many  people
    value  but few would pay fordirectly.  Advertising has an effect of
    transforming information from apublic into a private good. It makes
    possible for information providersto make profits by satisfying the
    tastes of large audiences for whosedesire  to  consume  information
    they are unable to charge directly.
       Thus, customer of goods orservices and citizen of any country –
    are in the same conditions. Likecustomers — citizens may have (and
    they have)  different  preferences for political information,  but
    citizens do not value  information about  politics only because it
    contributes to their ability to voteintelligently and customers do.
    Like customers — citizens’  tastes differ  in  many ways and  that
    generate wide  variations  in  the intensity  of  their demand for
    political information.
       Since it does not appear to betrue, that  political  information
    market  is  blocked  by  an ongoing  problem  of  undersupply,  the
    conventional justification forgranting the press broad freedom from
    legal liability for the harms itcauses must give away!  It does not
    necessarily mean that the economiccase for legal sanctions has been
    made.  Although  it  seems themarket could be relied upon to supply
    «enough» information.  Sothat subsidies in the form  of  protection
    from  legal  liability  are notneeded.  Personal responsibility and
    legal accountability would be 100% if the information market  could
    internalize to producers not onlythe benefits but also the costs of
    their activities & failures.  Asfor victims,  they’ll get one  more
    chance  to avoid the harms happenedfrom the production of defective
    information.
       Legal accountability for harm is desirable  in  a  market   that
    systematically  fails  to  punish «unfair»  producers for defective
    products. This kind of failureoccurs in two quite different cases:
    1) The first occasion has to do withthe market’s responsiveness  to
       the  demands of consumers.  Thefailure occurs when customers are
       unable to detect defects beforepurchase or to protect themselves
       by  taking appropriateprecautions after purchase,  when they are
       unable to translate their willingness to  pay  for  nondefective
       products  into  a  demand  that some  producers will satisfy and
       profit from. It also occurs whensuppliers are unable to gain any
       competitive  ad-  vantage either  by  exposing  defects in their
       rivals’ products or by toutingthe relative merits of their own.
    2) The second kind of market failureis an inability to  internalize
       harm  to bystanders — thirdparties who have no dealings with the
       producers but who just happen tobe in the  wrong  place  at  the
       wrong time when a productmalfunctions.  Even when these kinds of
       failures occur,  legalaccountability is problematic  if  it  in
       turn  entails  inevitable  error in  application or requires the
       taking  of  such  costly precautions  that  they  cover  up  all
       benefits.
       Conceiving of quality as  a function  of accuracy, relevance and
    comple- teness,  consumers ofpolitical information  are  not  in  a
    strong  position  when  it comes todetecting quality defects in the
    political information they receive. Revelance may  well  be  within
    their ken,  but since they are quiteunable to verify for themselves
    either the accuracy or thecompleteness of any particular account of
    political events.  In addition, since political information usually
    comes bundled  with  other entertainment  and  news  features  that
    sustain  their  loyality to particularsuppliers,  consumers are not
    inclined  to  punish  information producers  by   avoiding   future
    patronage even when they commit anoccasional gross error.
       Nevertheless, competition  amongjournalists  and  publishers  of
    political information tends tocreate  an  environment  that  is  in
    general  more  conductive  to accuracy than to lies or half-truths.
    Journalistic careers can be made by exposing  others’  errors,  and
    they  can  be  ruined  when  ajournalist is revealed to be careless

    about truth.  These realities createincentives for journalists  not
    to make mistakes.
       Moreover, the investment thatmainstream publishers and broadcas-
    ters make in their reputations forthoroughness and accuracy attests
    to the  market’s perceived abilityto detect and reward suppliers of
    consistently high- qualityinformation.  Information suppliers  that
    cater  to  more  specialized  tastesplay a significant role.  These
    alternative ways of getting info areoften probe apparent  realities
    more  deeply,  interprete  events with  greater  sophistication and
    analyse data more thoroughly thanthe mainstream media are  inclined
    to do.
       In doing so, of course,  theirprincipal motivation is to satisfy
    their own customers.  But whilepursuing this goal,  they  constrain
    (even  if  they  do not completelyeliminate) the mainstream media’s
    ability to portray falsehood astruth or  to  OMIT  key  facts  from
    otherwise apparently compeletepictures.
       The array  of  incentives  with respect  to at least the general
    quality of political information, with which the  market  confronts
    information  providers  creates systematic  tendencies  for them to
    provide political info that isaccurate and complete.  Or perhaps it
    would  be slightly more precise tosay that the market unfortunately
    does not appear systematically toreward producers of  falsehood  or
    half-truth information yet, according to their activities.  So that
    consumers of political informationdon’t  need  the  club  of  legal
    liability  to  force  information providers  to  provide  them with
    quality information.
       The analysts ought not to be readas an asserting that the reason
    the  market for politicalinformation works well is that it provides
    just the right kind and quality ofinformation  to  each  individual
    citizen  and  that each individualcitizen has identical preferences
    for info about government.  Indeed, the premise of this argument is
    that  the  market  works becausecitizens (or customers) do not have
    identical preferences and producersexploit  that  fact  by  finding
    ways  to  cater  to and profit fromthe varying demands of a diverse
    citizenry.   An   implicit  assumption   provides   the   normative
    underpinnings for the analysis. Obviously, the full implications of
    this assumption cannot be worked outhere.
       The claim  that  the  market  in general  «works»  shouldn’t  be
    understood as a claim that theinformation it generates is uniformly
    edifying and never distorted. As youknow many information producers
    pander  to the public’s appetite forscandal and still others see to
    it.  These facts do not  warrant the  conclusion  that  the  market
    doesn’t work.
       More significantly,  it  seems inconceivable  that any system of
    government regulation — including a  system  in  which  information
    producers  are  liable  for «defective» information — could in fact
    systematically  generate  a  flow of  political  information   that
    consistently  provided  more citizens with the quality and quantity
    that met their own needs as theythemselves defined  than  does  the
    competition in the marketplace ofideas that we presently enjoy.
       This analysis  suggests  that the  workings of the market create
    situation in which consumers ofpolitical information  do  not  need
    the  threat  of  producer liability  to  guarantee  that  they  are
    systematically getting a TRUSTWORTHYproduct.
       But consumers are not the only potential  victims  of  defective
    information and market incentivesare not always adequate to protect
    NONCONSUMER victims from the harm ofdefective information. Innocent
    bystanders,  such  as pedestrianshit by defective motorcycles,  are
    sometimes hurt by products overwhose producers they have no control
    either as consumers or competitors.Persons, who find themselves the
    unwitting subjects of defectiveinformation,  stand in an  analogous
    position.
       For example,   a   story  about sexual  assault  might  be  very
    interesting for public and mightserve well the public  interest  in
    being  informed about the policeefforts or criminal justice system.
    But the victim’s name is  NOT NECESSARY  to  its  purpose  and  its
    publication both invades her privacyand broke her safety.  In cases
    like this, it’s not so easy to haveconfidence in market incentives.
    The  harm  from  the  defect  is highly  concentrated on the single
    defamed or exposed individual.
       Now, it’s time to ask the majorquestion:  Should  the  press  be
    permitted  to  externalizeparticularized harms?  Why should not the
    press,  like other businessentities,  be liable when defects in its
    products  cause  particularized harmto individual third parties who
    have few means of self-protection attheir disposal?
       According to the Constitution, defamed public officials or  rape
    victims  should  have  access  to massmedia  for  rebuttal.  As for
    everyday practice,  the press is notalways eager to give  space  to
    claims  that it has erred.  Thereare two objections,  why the press
    shouldn’t be responsible for theharm of such  kind:  accountability
    to  a  more  demanding legalstandard would compromise its financial
    viability and undermine itsindependence.
       These objections are too SELF-SERVING  to  be  taken  completely
    seriously:  The  financial viability argument is no more persuasive
    when the product of the press harmsinnocent third parties  than  it
    is   when   other   manufacturers’  malfunctioning   products  harm
    bystanders.  As  press  doesn’t  underproduce   information,   thus
    «freedom» from liabilitycan’t be defended as necessary subsidy. The
    «financial viability»objection  points  toward  the  imposition  of
    liability for harm.
       The need  to  maintain  the press’s independence from government
    does provide  support  for  the press’s  objection  that  liability
    threatens  them  unduly.  But  it’s hard  to sustain the claim that
    government’s censorious hand wouldlurk behind a rule that  required
    the  press  to  compensete individuals.  It  is  not  obvious  that
    enforcing a rule that simply prohibitedpublishing the names of rape
    victims would signal the beginningof the end of our cherished press
    freedom.
       Asking whether the press shouldbe more legally accountable  than
    it  is now for publishing defamatoryfalsehoods about individuals or
    revealing rape victims’ namestouches a number of difficult,  highly
    discussed questions. In spite of thefact, by recasting a portion of
    the debate over legal accountabilityand by  focusing  attention  on
    the   disparity   of   legal treatment  between  producers  in  the
    information  market  and  those  in other  markets  for  goods  and
    services,  it  does  seem  possible to gain some fresh and possibly
    useful insight.
       The reality seems to be that,  withrespect to  the  quality  and
    quantity   of   political  information,  free  competition  in  the
    marketplace of ideas performs admirably,  with  inventive  ways  of
    overcoming  market  failure  and with  flexibility in adapting to a
    countless consumers preferences.
       In light of this reality it oughtnot to be amiss to suggest that
    when neither the threat ofincreasing a supposed undersupply nor the
    looming shadow of governmentcensorship is implicated, the massmedia
    should be liable for egregiouserrors.